Appendix E13

Evolution: The Myth of Neutral Origins / Closed-System Biology

I. Claim of Neutrality

Evolutionary theory presents itself as a sober, neutral account of life’s history. In classrooms, museums, and textbooks it is framed as just science: a descriptive framework that reports how organisms change over time, unburdened by philosophy or theology. The rhetoric is modest—no claims about meaning or purpose, only mechanisms: random variation filtered by natural selection. By adopting this posture, evolution secures a privileged status in public discourse: not one interpretation among others, but the baseline of rational inquiry against which other accounts are measured.

This aura of neutrality also functions polemically. Alternatives that invoke design, providence, or ontological ground are portrayed as importing “extra-scientific” commitments, while evolution is cast as commitment-free. Doubt of the evolutionary frame is therefore recoded as doubt of science itself. The effect is self-insulating: evolution’s claims are taken as fact before their premises are examined.

This section sets the stage for unmasking that posture. In what follows, we will show that the neutrality claim conceals a closed-system presupposition and that, when tested by a simple audit (the Cumulative Potentiation Test, CPT), the narrative of gradual construction fails on its own terms.

II. The Hidden Premise

Beneath the claim of neutrality lies a concealed assumption: that life must be explained as a closed system*. Evolutionary accounts begin not with evidence but with a methodological rule — that only natural causes may be considered. As a research discipline, such a rule has value: laboratories test mechanisms by bracketing off appeals to transcendent agency. We accept methodological naturalism as a laboratory rule; we contest its quiet conversion into metaphysical naturalism in origins-talk — where a rule of method is treated as a rule of reality.

This slippage is rarely acknowledged. What begins as a procedure for investigation becomes a prohibition against ontology: life must be explained without divine prerogative, as if possibility and order are self-originating. Every sudden appearance in the fossil record, every leap in complexity, every interdependent system is interpreted on the assumption that a purely material pathway exists, even when none is demonstrated. To step outside that frame — to consider God’s prerogative of type and instantiation — is dismissed as “unscientific.”

Thus, the supposed neutrality of evolution is itself a form of presuppositional exclusion. By foreclosing the question of ontological ground, it smuggles in a metaphysical commitment while disguising it as empirical modesty. The hidden premise of the evolutionary myth is not openness but closure: a biology that must remain self-sufficient, no matter what the evidence says.

III. The Critique: Scientistic Reductionism

Once the hidden premise is acknowledged, evolution is revealed not as neutral science but as a narrowed philosophy — scientistic reductionism. It assumes that whatever exists must be explained in terms of material processes alone, and that anything beyond those processes is either illusion or irrelevant. This posture reduces biology to a closed circle, where matter explains itself and possibility is presumed self-sufficient.

The reduction shows itself in several characteristic ways:

  • Models treated as explanations. Illustrative pathways — the eye imagined as a progression from patch to cup to lens — are presented as if they were evidence. Yet such models are exercises in plausibility, not demonstrations of mechanism. Analogy is mistaken for ontology. 

  • Models show conditional possibility (‘if these parameters, then this curve’). CPT asks for ordered intermediates with present advantage, preserved via sequential fixation; models only show conditional possibility. A model can illustrate; only evidence can instantiate. See below.

  • Descriptive laws mistaken for creative power. “Survival of the fittest,” more carefully phrased as differential reproductive success, describes how populations shift. But it explains nothing about the rise of new coordinated structures. Selection can prune; it cannot originate. A mechanism of subtraction is rhetorically recast as a source of novelty.

  • Gaps protected by rhetorical patches. The fossil record shows sudden appearances and missing intermediates. To defend the theory, concepts like punctuated equilibrium are invoked — a shift in tempo masquerading as a mechanism; it still supplies no ordered intermediates or fixation pathway. Yet such devices offer no ordered intermediates, no incremental advantages, and no pathway of fixation. They are linguistic maneuvers, not explanations.

  • Ontology replaced by chronology. Instead of addressing what makes new forms possible, the narrative defaults to time: given enough ages, improbable steps are assumed to have occurred. But chronology is not causation. Time does not generate ontology.

What passes itself off as empirical neutrality is therefore the elevation of method into metaphysic, and the reduction of ontology to narrative necessity. Evolution is not merely a description of biological change but a philosophical posture that confuses story for mechanism and assumes the creative power it seeks to prove.

IV. The Exposure: The Cumulative Potentiation Test (CPT)**

If evolutionary theory is to explain life’s complexity, it must do so on its own terms. By definition, natural selection can only preserve what already exists and confers an immediate benefit. For evolution to produce a complex system, mutations must not only occur but also be preserved in a sequence where each one is viable, advantageous, and enabling for the next. This requirement is what we may call cumulative potentiation.

To make this explicit, we can frame the Cumulative Potentiation Test (CPT):

  • CPT-1: Dependencies. Identify the minimal set of parts required for the system to function.

  • CPT-2: Order. Demonstrate the correct sequencing of those parts.

  • CPT-3:  Intermediate Advantage. Show that each stage provides an immediate survival or reproductive benefit. Here the Visibility Problem arises: many biological systems (e.g., meiosis, mitosis) require sub-phenotypic precision — spindle assembly, crossover checkpoints, error correction — that confer no advantage until fully expressed. Natural selection cannot “see” these invisible precursors, so they cannot be preserved incrementally. (See Abridged Exhibits below).

  • CPT-4: Scaffolds. If scaffolds or exaptations are invoked, show how they plausibly bridge the gap and why they can be removed.

  • CPT-5: Cross-Lineage Synchrony. For systems spanning multiple species, demonstrate how traits arise in coordination.

  • CPT-6: Sequential Fixation. Show how earlier beneficial mutations are preserved long enough for later complementary ones to arise in the same lineage. This difficulty is already anticipated in Haldane’s Dilemma: the “cost of natural selection” limits how many advantageous mutations can be fixed in a population over time. Even under generous assumptions, the rate of fixation is far too slow to account for the vast complexity observed.

    Sequential fixation is sometimes used in population genetics to describe the successive replacement of alleles by drift. Here it is used more strictly: the preservation of enabling mutations in ordered sequence, in the same lineage, until complementary steps arrive.

    Yet CPT-6 presses the problem further. It is not only that too few mutations can be fixed quickly enough; it is that the right mutations must appear in the right order and in the same lineage. Random variation offers no mechanism to cordon off an enabling step until its complement arrives. Let effective population size Ne, mutation rate μ, selection coefficient s, and step count k be generous; the expected waiting time τ(Ne,μ,s,k) for ordered enabling mutations in a single lineage grows super-linearly. Without a preservation mechanism, early steps are lost to drift or noise before later ones arise.

    Thus CPT-6 extends Haldane’s dilemma: even if the rate problem were solved, the sequencing problem remains. Evolutionary theory has no means to guarantee the stacking of mutations into an ordered, cumulative pathway.

Pass rule:  A pathway passes CPT only if every intermediate is (i) viable, (ii) confers net reproductive advantage now, (iii) appears in the required order, (iv) is plausibly scaffolded and de-scaffolded, (v) satisfies cross-lineage synchrony where relevant, and (vi) is sequentially fixable in the same lineage. A single failure yields explanatory deficit under CPT.

Here the sharpest difficulty lies in CPT-6: the Sequential Fixation Problem. Even if a beneficial mutation arises, there is no mechanism to cordon it off until another enabling mutation appears in the same lineage. Mutations are scattered, degraded by drift, or outweighed by noise before a cumulative chain can form. In practice, the waiting time for ordered steps grows far beyond realistic evolutionary scales.

When tested by CPT, flagship examples of evolutionary storytelling — from the vertebrate eye to the co-adaptation of bees and flowers — reveal profound deficits. Intermediates prove non-viable or non-advantageous, ordering is unworkable, scaffolds are speculative, and fixation is impossible. Instead of explanation, the theory offers semiotic effigiations: signs that simulate explanation. (See Glossary, Ontology and Semiotics essays.)

Case Study 1: The Eye

The vertebrate eye is often presented as evolution’s most persuasive example. From Darwin’s day to modern textbooks, the story is told: a patch of light-sensitive cells deepens into a cup, narrows into a pinhole, and gradually acquires a lens. With enough time, it is claimed, incremental refinements yield the precision optics of vertebrate vision. At first glance the progression seems smooth. Yet when tested by the Cumulative Potentiation Test (CPT), the pathway dissolves into assumption.

CPT-1: Dependencies. The eye is not one part but many: retina, cornea, lens, iris, muscles, tear film, and neural circuitry. None confer meaningful function alone. These therefore are functional and non-linear dependencies. Furthermore, Optical models (pinhole → lens) address optics, not systems integration (tear film, accommodation muscles, retinal preprocessing, cortical decoding, developmental control); CPT remains unmet.

CPT-2: Order. A lens without retina is useless; a retina without neural processing yields only noise; ocular muscles without optics achieve nothing. The system’s parts are not sequentially additive but mutually dependent.

CPT-3: Intermediate Advantage. Supposed intermediates, like shallow patches or pinholes, are claimed to be advantageous but rarely demonstrated to be so. Without clear reproductive benefit in their own time, such steps would vanish rather than accumulate.

CPT-4: Scaffolds. Exaptations are suggested — pigment spots as proto-retinas, transparent tissue as proto-lens. But scaffolds must plausibly bridge to precision and later be discarded. No account explains how intermediate tissues avoid being maladaptive before refinement. Optical improvement ≠ vision. Without accommodation, tear-film stability, retinal preprocessing, cortical decoding, and developmental control, optics deliver little selectable advantage.

CPT-5: Cross-Lineage Synchrony. The eye requires not only optics but neurological integration. Retinal input without cortical processing is blindness; cortical circuitry without retinal input is inert. Both must arise together.

CPT-6: Sequential Fixation. Even if a proto-lens emerged, there is no mechanism to “cordon it off” until complementary refinements appear in retina and neural pathways. Beneficial mutations disperse or degrade before ordered chains can form. The waiting time for such coordinated steps exceeds plausible evolutionary windows.

CPT Verdict: The eye demonstrate explanatory deficits, and most fatally at CPT-6. Evolutionary narratives of vision do not demonstrate viable pathways; they illustrate imagined plausibility. What is presented as neutral science is in fact a semiotic effigiation—(signs that simulate explanation). 

Case Study 2: Bees and Flowers

The symbiosis between bees and flowering plants is one of biology’s most celebrated marvels. Plants offer nectar and pollen; bees, in return, pollinate. The match is so precise that many flowers cannot reproduce without bees, and many bees cannot thrive without flowers. Evolutionary accounts frame this as “co-evolution”: flowers slowly adapted to attract pollinators, while bees gradually specialized to exploit floral resources. The narrative is elegant, but under the Cumulative Potentiation Test (CPT) it disintegrates.

CPT-1: Dependencies. Successful pollination requires a suite of traits on both sides. Plants need nectar secretion, corolla depth, and ultraviolet nectar guides. Bees need proboscis length, UV-sensitive eyes, olfactory tuning, and navigational behaviors such as the waggle dance. None of these features achieves function in isolation.

CPT-2: Order. Each system presupposes the other. A flower secreting nectar without pollinators expends energy wastefully; a bee with a long proboscis but no deep flowers gains nothing. The dependencies are reciprocal, not sequential.

CPT-3: Intermediate Advantage. Intermediates fail to confer benefit. A partially elongated corolla with no matching bee is maladaptive. A bee with UV vision but no UV-marked flowers is disadvantaged against simpler rivals.

CPT-4: Scaffolds. Exaptations are proposed: early flowers may have relied on wind pollination; bees may once foraged generally. But such scaffolds do not explain the leap to lock-and-key precision. They assume traits persist without advantage until matched, which is implausible. Generalist, diffuse pollination may act as a provisional scaffold, yet it does not produce final lock-and-key specificity; mismatches remain non-advantageous and cannot be banked awaiting complements.  

CPT-5: Cross-Lineage Synchrony. This is the most acute shortfall. The system requires not only ordered steps but synchronous potentiation across species. Traits must arise in parallel in both bees and flowers for the system to be viable. Evolution offers no mechanism for such synchrony.

CPT-6: Sequential Fixation. Even if one side produced a promising mutation — a flower secreting nectar, or a bee elongating its proboscis — there is no way to preserve it while waiting for the complementary trait to emerge in the other lineage. Beneficial steps cannot be held in reserve. The waiting time for mutual coordination vastly exceeds plausible timescales.

CPT Verdict: The bee–flower system fails CPT on nearly every point, but most decisively on CPT-5 and CPT-6. Generalist pollination may provide a provisional scaffold, yet it does not solve the problem of specialization: mismatched intermediates still confer no advantage (CPT-3), synchrony across species remains absent (CPT-5), and no mechanism guarantees fixation of complementary traits (CPT-6). Co-evolutionary explanations thus collapse into retrospective storytelling, projecting necessity onto what cannot be mechanistically demonstrated. What is offered as neutral science is, in reality, a semiotic effigiation — a model mistaken for evidence, preserving the myth of closed-system biology.

Abridged Exhibits

Beyond the eye and bee–flower symbiosis, other biological systems display the same pattern of explanatory deficit under CPT. Each reveals how evolutionary storytelling substitutes plausibility for mechanism.

Metamorphosis. Caterpillars and butterflies require two complete body plans plus the machinery of pupation. No stage is viable in isolation, and no incremental advantage explains the transformation. Fails CPT-2, CPT-3, CPT-6.

Meiosis — The Visibility Problem. Crossing-over, chromosomal reduction, and error-correction demand exquisite precision. Yet natural selection acts only on phenotype; sub-phenotypic mechanisms cannot be “seen” until fully expressed. How could undetectable precursors be preserved? This is a classic failure of CPT-3 (no intermediate advantage) and CPT-6 (no sequential fixation).

Immune System. Antigen recognition, clonal expansion, and immunological memory form an interdependent triad. None provides advantage without the others. Fails CPT-1, CPT-2, CPT-3.

Binocular Vision & Retinal Rivalry. Depth perception requires matched eyes, precise muscular control, cortical fusion, and neural suppression of rivalry. Partial intermediates (misaligned axes, fusion without suppression, or a second eye without cortical integration) are maladaptive rather than advantageous. No ordering sequence or fixation pathway can account for the coordinated system. Fails CPT-1, CPT-2, CPT-3, CPT-6.

Bombardier Beetle. Its defensive spray requires two chemical precursors, inhibitor enzymes, storage chambers, and a release valve. Partial chemistry is lethal. Fails CPT-1, CPT-2.

Male/Female Complementarity. Reproductive anatomy and physiology must arise in reciprocal alignment across sexes. Any mismatch yields sterility, erasing the lineage. Requires synchrony and sequential fixation across two populations. Fails CPT-5, CPT-6.

V. Submetaphysical Diagnosis

The deficits exposed by CPT are not merely technical puzzles in biology. They reveal a deeper philosophical and moral pattern: the attempt to narrate possibility without an ontological ground. Evolutionary theory, presented as neutral science, is in fact a closed metaphysic. It borrows the fruits of order while denying the Source of order, smuggling in metaphysical commitments under the guise of empirical modesty.

Ontological Shortfall. Evolution assumes for itself the authority to generate new types. Yet the prerogative to define what may exist (auctoritas essendi) and to instantiate it (auctoritas instantiandi) belongs to the One True God alone — the Double Divine Prerogative (see Ontology Part I ). To attribute creative power to blind process is not explanation but usurpation.

Epistemological Evasion. Evolutionary storytelling confuses narrative with truth. Because a system exists now, it is said to have evolved. This is retrospective teleology, not disclosure of cause. Truth does not emerge from narrative reconstruction; it confronts the knower as ontological disclosure.

Moral Suppression. The refusal to acknowledge explanatory deficits is not a neutral oversight but a moral posture. To preserve autonomy from divine confrontation, materialist science tolerates improbabilities and contradictions it would reject elsewhere. This is rebellion masked as reason.

Semiotic Fraud. Evolutionary discourse thrives on effigiations — signs that simulate explanation without grounding it. “Pinhole to lens,” “punctuated equilibrium,” “co-evolution” — these are rhetorical constructions that preserve the myth of closed-system origins but collapse under CPT analysis.

Pragmatic Shielding. In public debate, the refrain “it evolved gradually” functions less as evidence than as closure. It deflects scrutiny, presumes sufficiency, and shields the myth from ontological confrontation. CPT unmasks this shield as empty: beneath the language lies no mechanism, no potentiation, no ground.

VI. Additional Points to Ponder

The deficits exposed by CPT are reinforced by broader patterns in the biological and fossil records. These are not minor anomalies but recurring tensions that evolutionary theory minimizes or explains away through rhetorical devices. Taken together, they underscore that the problem is not local but structural.

Cambrian Explosion. The sudden appearance of major phyla in a narrow geological window contradicts gradualism. Instead of sequential emergence, we find simultaneity. Appeals to “punctuated equilibrium” alter tempo but provide no mechanism that satisfies CPT.

Early Morphological Disparity. Rather than saying “fossil diversity was higher in the past,” it is more precise to note that morphological disparity — the range of body plans seen in the Cambrian — far exceeds later periods, despite ongoing taxonomic turnover. This reversal of expectation sits uneasily with a model of gradual, additive expansion.

Body Size Trajectories. Popular evolutionary narratives often imagine a progression from small/simple to large/complex. Yet the fossil record preserves counter-patterns: megafauna and giant insects dominate earlier strata, while many present forms are reduced in scale. This inversion aligns better with a story of subtraction and degeneration than of cumulative enlargement.

Natural Selection as Subtraction. Selection is eliminative, removing weaker variants. Yet it is rhetorically cast as creative — as though subtraction yields addition. This is not a mechanism but a semantic inversion.

Genotype–Phenotype Mismatch. Selection acts only on visible traits. Yet the machinery of inheritance — meiosis, mitosis, DNA repair, crossover — must be fully precise before it can be expressed. How could undetectable precursors be preserved by selection?

These points, long acknowledged at the margins, are rarely faced squarely. Instead they are rebranded, minimized, or cordoned off as “exceptions.” Their cumulative weight confirms that the deficits revealed by CPT are not isolated failures but symptoms of a deeper collapse in the explanatory framework.

VII. Conclusion

Adaptation is not in dispute. Microevolutionary shifts — such as bacterial resistance to antibiotics or variation in beak size — are well observed. These changes demonstrate the flexibility of existing systems, but they do not generate new ones. They typically arise by recombining, reducing, or tweaking what is already present.

The claim of evolutionary theory goes far beyond this. It is not simply that organisms adapt, but that architectural novelties — eyes, meiosis, immune systems, sexual complementarity — can emerge through the same mechanism. Here the difference is decisive: adaptation modifies; evolution is said to originate. And it is at the level of origination that the Cumulative Potentiation Test (CPT) applies, and where evolutionary theory consistently fails.

Elimination alone does not account for the origin of coordinated architectures. Selection can prune, refine, or reduce, but it cannot explain the construction of multi-module systems that demand ordered, cumulative potentiation. When tested by CPT, evolutionary pathways fail their own requirement. Complex systems such as the vertebrate eye, the bee–flower partnership, metamorphosis, meiosis, immune defense, and sexual complementarity reveal not ordered accumulation but explanatory deficit. Intermediates are non-viable, sequencing is incoherent, scaffolds are speculative, and above all, no mechanism exists for sequential fixation — the preservation of enabling steps until complemented. The supposed engine of cumulative progress stalls at the first turn.

The deeper problem is philosophical. Evolution substitutes story for ontology, plausibility for mechanism, and rhetoric for reality. It relies on effigiations — narratives that simulate explanation — to preserve the myth of closed-system origins. But possibility is not self-originating. Order does not arise from subtraction. Complexity does not emerge from blind process. Truth does not accumulate; it confronts.

Thus the failure of cumulative potentiation exposes more than gaps in biology. It unmasks the inadequacy of the metaphysic beneath it. Only God holds the prerogative to define kinds and instantiate possibility. To suppress this is not neutrality but a philosophical closure that pre-decides permissible answers. To acknowledge it is to recover the ground of ontology, the integrity of epistemology, and the possibility of knowledge.

The myth of neutral origins collapses under its own weight. What remains is the confrontation it has long sought to evade: life does not bear witness to the sufficiency of matter, but to the sufficiency of the One True God. 


Footnotes.

* Closed-system biology assumes that life must be explained by material processes alone. It begins as methodological naturalism but drifts into metaphysical naturalism, closing off ontology in advance. Its explanatory resource is time and chance, with truth recast as narrative plausibility. By contrast, an open-system ontology affirms methodological discipline without foreclosing transcendent agency. Possibility is disclosed by divine prerogative, not self-generated. Here truth confronts the knower, not as a story of emergence but as ontological disclosure.

**The Cumulative Potentiation Test (CPT) is developed here as a structured audit of proposed evolutionary pathways. It draws attention to six necessary conditions (Dependencies, Order, Intermediate Advantage, Scaffolds, Cross-Lineage Synchrony, Sequential Fixation), all of which must be satisfied for cumulative plausibility. This framework builds upon, but is distinct from, prior critiques. Haldane’s dilemma (1957) highlighted the rate-limit to beneficial substitutions, and Behe’s irreducible complexity (1996) emphasized the non-functionality of partial systems. CPT incorporates these insights but extends them: it unifies rate and order constraints, adds the requirement of inter-species synchrony, and foregrounds the problem of sequential fixation—the preservation of enabling mutations until complemented. In this sense, CPT does not replace existing critiques but systematizes them into an explicit falsifiability test.


PREVIOUS NEXT